Реферат: Euthanasia Essay Research Paper EuthanasiaEuthanasia also known

Название: Euthanasia Essay Research Paper EuthanasiaEuthanasia also known
Раздел: Топики по английскому языку
Тип: реферат

Euthanasia Essay, Research Paper

Euthanasia

Euthanasia, also known as mercy killing, is enveloped as deeply in

medical and ethical controversy as abortion. Both issues involve the termination

of a life, and both conjure strong arguments for advocacy and opposition.

Pro-euthanasia arguments emphasize the right of patients to choose their own

death, the duty of the physician to end pain and suffering, and the ability of

legalization to establish guidelines which create lucidity on when and how

euthanasia should be performed. Anti-euthanasia arguments, on the other hand,

emphasize the sanctity of life, the commitment of physicians to save lives, and the

possible dangers of mistakes. These are all important considerations. However,

in determining the ethics of euthanasia: religious values, opinions of the morality

involved, and interpretations of physician commitments should take a second seat

to the consideration of whether pain and suffering is uncontrollable, whether a

patient has a chance of recovering, and the development of extensive guidelines

by which physicians can make better decisions regarding euthanasia.

The definition of euthanasia can be subdivided into two parts: active and

passive. Passive euthanasia, the version deemed more acceptable by most

anti-euthanasia advocates, means simply refraining from rendering medical

treatment to keep the patient alive. This could mean withholding of medication

or life-sustaining therapy, refusing surgery, or negating to resuscitate and letting

the patient die of his or her own affliction (Darley 1). The definition of medical

treatment has been recently expanded by the American Medical Association to

encompass intravenous feeding and hydrating tubes. These medical devices used

to be considered a part of human care, which cannot be withheld from a patient.

Now that they are considered medical treatment, they can (Smith 1).

As a result of this, a patient may now die from starvation or dehydration

because of lack of intravenous nutrition and water supply. This has raised issues

in euthanasia debates over the humanity of such practices. Tom Flynn, an editor

for Free Inquiry, wrote an account of his partner s grandmother which describes

how, after terminating medical treatment on his grandmother, Flynn and his

partner had to watch her slowly die over a period of two weeks. In a descriptive

account of the inhumanity of the situation, Flynn wrote how Occasionally a

nurse or a family member would squeeze a few drops of water into her parched

and crackling mouth, but aside from a continuing dose of painkillers, that was all

she received (Flynn 1).

Common sense regarding the treatment of this situation did not come into

play here. If the decision is made to terminate treatment with the intention of

letting the person die a dignified death, and to end prolonged pain and suffering,

then it seems only logical to make sure that the patient does in fact reach a fast

and painless end after the fact. However, passive euthanasia, by definition, does

not provide for intervention after medical treatment has been terminated. Oddly

enough, this method of assisted suicide is considered by many religious

conservatives and anti-euthanasia advocates to be the humane method of

physician assisted suicide (1).

The inhumane method has been designated as active euthanasia. By

definition, active euthanasia can be described as taking some action designed to

directly bring about the end of a patient s life (Cherny 1). Throughout history,

cases of active euthanasia have caused much controversy. Michigan, in

particular, has been the setting for a number of incidences where people have

come to legal complications in situations where they helped another end his or

her life. In 1920 the Michigan State Supreme Court upheld the murder conviction

of a man who placed poison within the reach of his dying spouse who was

suffering from multiple sclerosis. This case, known as the People v. Campbell,

went unrecognized as a precedent sixty-three years later by a Michigan appellate

court which dismissed a murder charge against a man who gave a gun to a person

who was talking of committing suicide, and subsequently killed himself

(McCord 1).

Michigan was also the setting for the notorious Dr. Jack Kevorkian, who

orchestrated the infamous suicide of Janet Adkins in 1990. Adkins was suffering

from Alzheimer s disease, and in anticipation of years of degeneration from the

disease, requested the help of the doctor. Kevorkian reported himself to the

police immediately after she died. The murder charges brought on Kevorkian as a

result of his actions were dropped two years later, again ignoring the precedent of

Campbell s case. This lack of both continuity between cases, and established

policy with which to act upon, is symbolic of the same lack within the medical

field regarding active euthanasia.

Arguments against active euthanasia revolve around the notions that

physicians cannot always know the wishes of the patient, especially when the

patient is comatose or unresponsive; physicians hold an obligation to save and

prolong lives, not end them; physicians cannot always accurately gauge how

much time is left; and also that physicians can misdiagnose and label a patient as

terminal when in fact he or she has good chances of survival (1). In a discussion

of this, Wesley J. Smith, an editor for National Review, reported in 1995 that:

According to a growing body of medical literature, misdiagnosis of the

persistent vegetative state is a real problem. A study published in the

June 1991 Archives of Neurology found that, of 84 patients with a

firm diagnosis of persistent vegetative state, 58 percent recovered

consciousness within three years. Moreover, researchers were unable

to identify objective predictors of recovery to differentiate between

those who would awaken and those who would not. (Smith 1)

The issue of misdiagnosis could be seen as reason to say that the practice

of euthanasia should not be accepted, and a patients right to a death with dignity

should be denied. However, interpreting the issue this way is also another way of

saying that a person must continue in his or her suffering, regardless of whether

the cause is to prolong his or her life. Instead, misdiagnosis should be interpreted

as a factor that contributes to the need for more extensive guidelines in physician

assisted suicide. Guidelines which provide for the amount of time a person

should remain comatose or in pain before euthanasia is considered, especially

when the duration of such afflictions is uncertain, are some that definitely need to

be established. Malcolm Dean, an editor for the British publication The Lancet,

commented in 1995 that Doctors have too little guidance in mercy killing

matters and there has been too little attention paid to the issue in medical

education and training (Dean 1).

Even if this void in medical treatment is remedied, still present is the

disturbing irony that some believe it is more humane to let a person die slowly of

starvation and thirst rather than give the person a remedy that will bring about a

faster, painless end. Realizing this irony would lead any logically minded person

to believe that the moral values regarding this issue are hypocritical and mundane.

The real focus should be on making sure euthanasia is done correctly, at the right

time, and is the best decision for the patient. With all the attention being placed

on sanctity of life, interpretation of the physician s oath, and legality involved;

policy and procedure are going to have a tough time being established with so

many barricades to battle through.

Works Cited

Cherny, Nathan I. The Problem of Inadequately Relieved Suffering.

(Psychological Perspectives on Euthanasia). Journal of Social Issues.

Summer 1996: 52, 2, 13.

Darley, John M. Community Attitudes on the Family of Issues Surrounding the

Death of Terminally Ill Patients. Journal of Social Issues. Summer

1996: 52, 2, 85. la.edu.

Dean, Malcolm. Politics of Euthanasia in the UK The Lancet. 18 March 1995:

345, 8951, 714.

Flynn, Tom. A Case For Mercy Killing. Free Inquiry. Summer 1993: 13, 3,

60.

McCord, William. Death With Dignity. The Humanist. Jan.-Feb. 1993: 53, 1,

26.

Smith, Wesley J. Killing Grounds: By Dehumanizing Brain Damaged Patients,

We Have Made It Acceptable to Starve or Dehydrate Themselves to

Death. National Review. 6 March 1995: 47, n4, 54.