Косвенные речевые акты в современном английском языке

CONTENTS

INTRODUCTIONтАжтАжтАжтАжтАж.тАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАж.3

1. INDIRECT SPEECH ACTS: FORM VERSUS FUNCTIONтАжтАжтАжтАж5

2. WHY DO SPEAKERS HAVE TO BE INDIRECT?тАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАж.7

2.1. The cooperative principleтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАж.7

2.2. The theory of politeness тАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАж..8

3. HOW DO HEARERS DISCOVER INDIRECT SPEECH ACTS

AND тАЬDECIPHERтАЭ THEIR MEANING?тАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАж.10

3.1. The inference theoryтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАж..10

3.2. Indirect speech acts as idioms?тАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАж..тАж12

3.3. Other approaches to the problemтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАж13

4. ILLOCUTIONS OF INDIVIDUAL UTTERANCES WITHIN A

DISCOURSEтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАж.14

5.INDIRECT SPEECH ACTS IN ENGLISH AND UKRAINIANтАжтАж.16

6.EXAMPLES OF INDIRECT SPEECH ACTS IN MODERN

ENGLISH DISCOURSEтАжтАжтАж.тАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАж.18

6.1. FictionтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАж18

6.2. PublicismтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАж20

6.3. AdvertisingтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАж.21

6.4. AnecdotesтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАж..21

7. INDIRECT SPEECH ACTS AS A YARDSTICK OF COMMUNI-

CATIVE MATURITY AND MUTUAL UNDERSTANDING тАж.тАж.23

CONCLUSIONSтАжтАжтАж.тАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАж.25

РЕЗЮМЕтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАж.тАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАж.27

LITERATUREтАж.тАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАжтАж.28

INTRODUCTION

тАЬA great deal can be said in the study of

language without studying speech acts,

but any such purely formal theory is

necessarily incomplete. It would be as if

baseball were studied only as a formal

system of rules and not as a game.тАЭ

John Rogers Searle

In the late 1950s, the Oxford philosopher John Austin gave some lectures on how speakers тАЬdo things with wordsтАЭ and so invented a theory of тАЬspeech actsтАЭ [10, 40] which now occupies the central place in pragmatics (pragmatics is the study of how we use language to communicate in a particular context). Austin highlighted the initial contrast between the constative and the performative. While constatives describe a state of affairs, performatives (explicit and implicit) have the potential to bring about a change in some state of affairs. Classical examples of performatives include the naming of a ship, the joining of two persons in marriage, and the sentencing of a criminal by an authorised person. Austin distinguished between the locution of a speech act (the words uttered), its illocution (the intention of the speaker in making the utterance) and its perlocution(its effects, intended or otherwise). Whereas constatives typically have truth conditions to comply with, speech acts must satisfy certain тАЬfelicity conditionsтАЭ in order to count as an action: there must be a conventional procedure; the circumstances and people must be appropriate; the procedure must be executed correctly and completely; often, the persons must have the requisite thoughts, feelings, etc.

John AustinтАЩs theory of speech acts was generalized to cover all utterances by a student of Austin's, John Rogers Searle [43, 69]. Searle showed that we perform speech acts every time we speak. For example, asking тАЬWhat's the time?тАЭ we are performing the speech act of making a request. Turning an erstwhile constative into an explicit performative looks like this: тАЬIt is now ten oтАЩclockтАЭ means тАЬI hereby pronounce that it is ten oтАЩ clock in the morning.тАЭ

In such a situation, the original constative versus performative distinction becomes untenable: all speech is performative. The important distinction is not between the performative and the constative, but between the different kinds of speech acts being performed, that is between direct and indirect speech acts. Searle's hypothesis was that in indirect speech acts, the speaker communicates the non-literalas well as the literal meaningto the hearer. This new pragmatic trend was named intentionalism because it takes into account the initial intention of the speaker and its interpretation by the hearer.

Actuality of research:

The problem of indirect speech acts has got a great theoretical meaning for analysis of the form/function relation in language: the same form performs more than one function. To generate an indirect speech act, the speaker has to use qualitatively different types of knowledge, both linguistic and extralinguistic (interactive and encyclopaedic), as well as the ability to reason [45, 97]. A number of theories try to explain why we make indirect speech acts and how we understand their non-literal meaning, but the research is still far from being complete.

The practical value of research lies in the fact that it is impossible to reach a high level of linguistic competence without understanding the nature of indirect speech acts and knowing typical indirect speech acts of a particular language.

The tasks of research:

1) analysis of the theories on indirect speech acts;

2) finding out why interlocutors generate indirect speech acts instead of saying exactly what they mean;

3) comparing typical indirect speech acts in English and in Ukrainian;

4) providing examples of indirect speech acts in various communicational situations.

The object of research is a speech act as a communicational action that speakers perform by saying things in a certain way in a certain context.

The subject of research is an indirect speech act as the main way in which the semantic content of a sentence can fail to determine the full force and content of the illocutionary act being performed in using the sentence.

Methods of research include critical analysis of scientific works on the subject, analysis of speech of native English speakers in various communicational situations, analysis of speech behavior of literary personages created by modern British and American writers.

1. INDIRECT SPEECH ACTS: FORM VERSUS FUNCTION

тАЬCommunication is successful not when

hearers recognize the linguistic meaning of the

utterance, but when they infer the speaker's

meaning from it.тАЭ

Dan Sperber and Deidre Wilson

Most of what human beings say is aimed at success of perlocutionary acts, but because perlocutionary effects are behavioural, cognitive, or emotional responses they are not linguistic objects. What linguists can properly look at, however, are the intentions of speakers to bring about certain perlocutionary effects which are called illocutionary intentions.

The basis of a speech act is the speakerтАЩs intention to influence the hearer in a desired way. The intention can be manifested and latent. According to O.G. Pocheptsov [13,74], latent intentions cannot be linguistically analyzed while manifested intentions can be divided into evident and inferable. The illocutinary intention of indirect speech acts is inferable.

Three broad illocutionary categories are normally identified тАУ a statement, a question and a command/request - having typical realisations in declarative, interrogative and imperative verb forms. But sometimes the syntactic form of a sentence is not a good guide to the act it is performing. In indirect speech acts the agreement between the intended function and the realised form breaks down, and the outward (locutionary) form of an utterance does not correspond with the intended illocutionary force of the speech act which it performs [37, 263]. In indirection a single utterance is the performance of one illocutionary act by way of performing another. Indirect speech acts have two illocutionary forces [45, 195].

SearleтАЩs classical example of an indirect speech act is the utterance тАЬCan you pass the salt?тАЭ Without breaking any linguistic norms we can regard it as a general question and give a yes/no answer. But most often hearers interpret it as a request. Likewise, the utterance тАЬThere's a fly in your soupтАЭ may be a simple assertion but, in a context, a warning not to drink the soup. The question тАЬWhat's the time?тАЭ might, when one is looking for an excuse to get rid of an unwelcome guest, be intended as a suggestion that the guest should leave. Analogously, the statement тАЬI wouldn't do this if I were youтАЭ has the congruent force of an imperative: тАЬDon't do it!тАЭ

In his works Searle gives other interesting examples of indirect speech acts: Why donтАЩt you be quiet? It would be a good idea if you gave me the money now. How many times have I told you (must I tell you) not to eat with your fingers? I would appreciate it if you could make less noise. In some contexts these utterances combine two illocutionary forces and sound idiomatic, even though they are not idioms in the proper sense of the term. Each utterance contains an imperative (secondary illocution) realized by means of a question or a statement (primary illocution).

Paul Grice illustrates indirectness by the following utterances [4, 22]: тАЬThere is a garage around the cornerтАЭ used to tell someone where to get petrol, and тАЬMr. X's command of English is excellent, and his attendance has been regularтАЭ, giving the high points in a letter of recommendation. A simple example of an indirect speech act gives B.Russel: тАЬWhen parents say тАШPuddle!тАЩ to their child, what they mean is тАШDonтАЩt step into it!тАЩ [41, 195]. These are examples in which what is meant is not determined by what is said.

We can make a request or give permission by way of making a statement, e.g. by uttering тАЬI am getting thirsty.тАЭ or тАЬIt doesn't matter to me.тАЭ We can make a statement or give an order by way of asking a question, such as тАЬWill the sun rise tomorrow?тАЭ or тАЬCan you clean up your room?тАЭWhen an illocutionary act is performed indirectly, it is performed by way of performing some other one directly.

It has been found that indirect expressives, directives and representatives compose the most numerous group of indirect speech acts [11, 23].

The study of indirect speech acts has mostly dealt with requests in various guises. Jerrold M. Sadock identified some exotic species: тАЬwhimperativesтАЭ - indirect requests in the form of a question, e.g. тАЬCan't you (please) do something?тАЭ and тАЬDo something, will you?тАЭ; тАЬqueclarativesтАЭ - the speaker directly questions and indirectly makes an assertion: тАЬDoes anyone do A any more?тАЭ meaning "Nobody does A any more"; тАЬrequestionsтАЭ are quiz questions to which the speaker knows the answer, e.g. Columbus discovered America in ..?[42, 168].

Summarizing, we can say that indirection is the main way in which the semantic content of a sentence can fail to determine the full force and content of the illocutionary act being performed in using the sentence.

2. WHY DO SPEAKERS HAVE TO BE INDIRECT?

тАЬEverything that is worded too directly nowadays

runs the risk of being socially condemned.тАЭ

Ye.Klyuev

2.1. The cooperative principle

An insight into indirectness is based on the Cooperative Principle developed by Paul Grice [4, 14-76]: language users tacitly agree to cooperate by making their contributions to the conversation to further it in the desired direction. Grice endeavoured to establish a set of general principles explaining how language users convey indirect meanings (so-called conversational implicatures, i.e. implicit meanings which have to be inferred from what is being said explicitly, on the basis of logical deduction). Adherence to this principle entails that speakers simultaneously observe 4 maxims:

1) Maxim of Quality:

- Do not say what you believe to be false.

- Do not say that for which you lack adequate evidence.

2) Maxim of Relevance:

- Be relevant.

3) Maxim of Quantity:

- Make your contribution as informative as required.

- Do not make your contribution more informative than is required.

4) Maxim of Manner:

- Avoid obscurity of expression.

- Avoid ambiguity.

- Be brief.

- Be orderly.

This general description of the normal expectations we have in conversations helps to explain a number of regular features in the way people say things. For instance, the common expressions "Well, to make a long story short" or "I won't bore you with the details" indicate an awareness of the maxims of quantity and manner. Because we assume that other speakers are following these maxims, we often draw inferences based on this assumption.

At one level, cooperative behaviour between the interactants means that the conversational maxims are being followed; but at another and more important level, cooperative behaviour still operates even if the conversational maxims are apparently broken. For instance, when the speaker blatantly and openly says something which appears to be irrelevant and ambiguous (flouts the maxims of relevance and manner), it can be assumed that s/he really intends to communicate something which is relevant and unambiguous, but does so implicitly:

тАЬ - I don't suppose you could manage tomorrow evening?

- How do you like to eat?

- Actually I rather enjoy cooking myself.тАЭ [J. Fowles]

The second remark, instead of being a direct answer (a statement), is a question formally not connected with the first remark. The maxims of relevance and manner are flouted. The inferable implicature is: тАЬYes, I can.тАЭAnalogously, the implication of the third remark is inferred: тАЬI invite you to have dinner at my place.тАЭ

If we were forced to draw only logical inferences, life would be a lot more difficult. Conversations would take longer since we would have to say things which reasonable language-users currently infer.

Searle adds one more conversational maxim [45, 126]: тАЬSpeak idiomatically unless you have a reason not to.тАЭ He exemplifies this maxim like this: if we say archaically тАЬKnowest thou him who calleth himself Richard Nixon?тАЭ (not idiomatically), the utterance will not be perceived as a usual question тАЬDo you know Richard Nixon?тАЭ

An important difference between implicatures and what is said directly is that the speaker can always renounce the implicatures s/he hinted at. For example, in тАЬLove and friendshipтАЭ by A.Lourie the protagonist answers to a lady asking him to keep her secret: тАЬA gentleman never talks of such thingsтАЭ. Later the lady finds out that he did let out her secret, and the protagonist justifies himself saying: тАЬI never said I was a gentleman.тАЭ

Implicatures put a question of insincerity and hypocrisy people resort to by means of a language (it is not by chance that George Orwell introduced the word тАЬto double speakтАЭ in his novel тАЬ1984тАЭ). No doubt, implicatures are always present in human communication. V.Bogdanov notes that numerous implicatures raise the speakerтАЩs and the hearerтАЩs status in each otherтАЩs eyes: the speaker sounds intelligent and knowledgeable about the nuances of communication, and the hearer realizes that the speaker relies on his shrewdness. тАЬCommunication on the implicature level is a prestigious type of verbal communication. It is widely used by educated people: to understand implicatures, the hearer must have a proper intellectual level.тАЭ (Богданов 1990:21).

The ancient rhetorician Demetrius declared the following: тАЬPeople who understand what you do not literally say are not just your audience. They are your witnesses, and well-wishing witnesses at that. You gave them an occasion to show their wit, and they think they are shrewd and quick-witted. But if you тАЬchew overтАЭ your every thought, your hearers will decide your opinion of their intellect is rather low.тАЭ (Деметрий 1973:273).

2.2. The theory of politeness

Another line of explanation of indirectness is provided by a sociolinguistic theory of politeness developed in the late 1970s. Its founder Geoffrey Leech introduced the politeness principle: people should minimize the expression of impolite beliefs and maximize the expression of polite beliefs [36, 102]. According to the politeness theory, speakers avoid threats to the тАЬfaceтАЭ of the hearers by various forms of indirectness, and thereby тАЬimplicateтАЭ their meanings rather than assert them directly. The politeness theory is based on the notion that participants are rational beings with two kinds of тАЬface wantsтАЭ connected with their public self-image [26, 215]:

тАв positive face - a desire to be appreciated and valued by others; desire for approval;

тАв negative face - concern for certain personal rights and freedoms, such as autonomy to choose actions, claims on territory, and so on; desire to be unimpeded.

Some speech acts (тАЬface threatening actsтАЭ) intrinsically threaten the faces. Orders and requests, for instance, threaten the negative face, whereas criticism and disagreement threaten the positive face. The perpetrator therefore must either avoid such acts altogether (which may be impossible for a host of reasons, including concern for her/his own face) or find ways of performing them with mitigating of their face threatening effect. For example, an indirectly formulated request (a son to his father) тАЬAre you using the car tonight?тАЭ counts as a face-respecting strategy because it leaves room for father to refuse by saying тАЬSorry, it has already been taken (rather than the face-threatening тАЬYou may not use itтАЭ). In that sense, the speakerтАЩs and the hearerтАЩs faces are being attended to.

Therefore, politeness is a relative notion not only in its qualitative aspect (what is considered to be polite), but in its quantitative aspect as well (to what degree various language constructions realize the politeness principle). Of course there are absolute markers of politeness, e.g. тАЬpleaseтАЭ, but they are not numerous. Most of language units gain a certain degree of politeness in a context.

3. HOW DO HEARERS DISCOVER INDIRECT SPEECH ACTS AND тАЬDECIPHERтАЭ THEIR MEANING?

It has been pointed out above that in indirect speech acts the relationship between the words being uttered and the illocutionary force is often oblique. For example, the sentence тАЬThis is a pig styтАЭ might be used nonliterally to state that a certain room is messy and filthy and, further, to demand indirectly that it be cleaned up. Even when this sentence is used literally and directly, say to describe a certain area of a barnyard, the content of its utterance is not fully determined by its linguistic meaning - in particular, the meaning of the word тАЬthisтАЭ does not determine which area is being referred to.

How do we manage to define the illocution of an utterance if we cannot do that by its syntactic form? There are several theories trying to answer this question.

3.1. The inference theory

The basic steps in the inference of an indirect speech act are as follows [37, 286-340]:

I. The literal meaning and force of the utterance are computed by, and available to, the participants.The key to understanding of the literal meaning is the syntactical form of the utterance.

II. There is some indication that the literal meaning is inadequate (тАЬa triggerтАЭ of an indirect speech act).

According to Searle, in indirect speech acts the speaker performs one illocutionary act but intends the hearer to infer another illocution by relying on their mutually shared background information, both linguistic and nonlinguistic, as well as on general powers of rationality and inference, that is on illocutionary force indicating devices[43, 73]. The illocutionary point of an utterance can be discovered by an inferential process that attends to the speaker's prosody, the context of utterance, the form of the sentence, the tense and mood of verbs, knowledge of the language itself and of conversational conventions, and general encyclopaedic knowledge. The speaker knows this and speaks accordingly, aware that the hearer - as a competent social being and language user - will recognize the implications [32, 41]. So, indirectness relies on conversational implicature: there is overwhelming evidence that speakers expect hearers to draw inferences from everything that is uttered. It follows that the hearer will begin the inferential process immediately on being presented with the locution. Under the cooperative principle, there is a convention that the speaker has some purpose for choosing this very utterance in this particular context instead of maintaining silence or generating another utterance. The hearer tries to guess this purpose, and in doing so, considers the context, beliefs about normal behaviour in this context, beliefs about the speaker, and the presumed common ground.

The fact that divergence between the form and the contents of an utterance can vary within certain limits helps to discover indirect speech acts: an order can be disguised as a request, a piece of advice or a question, but it is much less probable as a compliment.

III. There are principles that allow us to derive the relevantindirect forcefrom the literal meaning and the context.

Searle suggests that these principles can be stated within his theory of felicity conditions for speech acts [44, 38].

For example, according to SearleтАЩs theory, a command or a request has the following felicity conditions:

1. Asking or stating the preparatory condition:

Can you pass the salt?The hearer's ability to perform an action is being asked.

Literally it is a question; non-literally it is a request.

2. Asking or stating the propositional content:

You're standing on my foot. Would you kindly get off my foot?

Literally it is a statement or a question; non-literally it is a request.

3. Stating the sincerity condition:

I'd like you to do this for me.

Literally it is a statement; non-literally it is a request.

4. Stating or asking the good/overriding reasons for doing an action:

You had better go now. Hadn't you better go now?Why not go now?

Literally it is a statement or a question; non-literally it is a request.

5. Asking if a person wants/wishes to perform an action:

Would you mind helping me with this?Would you mind if I asked youif you could write me a reference?

Literally it is a question; non-literally it is a request (in the last example an explicit directive verb is embedded).

All these indirect acts have several common features:

1. Imperative force is not part of the literal meaning of these sentences.

2. These sentences are not ambiguous.

3. These sentences are conventionally used to make requests. They often have "please" at end or preceding the verb.

4. These sentences are not idioms, but are idiomatically used as requests.

5. These sentences can have literal interpretations.

6. The literal meanings are maintained when they question the physical ability: Can you pass the salt? - No,itтАЩs too far from me. I canтАЩt reach it.

7. Both the literal and the non-literal illocutionary acts are made when making a report on the utterance:

The speaker: Can you come to my party tonight?

The hearer: I have to get up early tomorrow.

Report: He said he couldn't come. OR:He said he had to get up early next morning.

A problem of the inference theory is that syntactic forms with a similar meaning often show differences in the ease in which they trigger indirect speech acts:

a) Can you reach the salt?

) Are you able to reach the salt?

c) Is it the case that you at present have the ability to reach the salt?

While (a) is most likely to be used as a request, (b) is less likely, and (c) is highly unlikely, although they seem to express the same proposition.

Another drawback of the inference theory is the complexity of the algorithm it offers for recognizing and deciphering the true meaning of indirect speech acts. If the hearer had to pass all the three stages every time he faced an indirect speech act, identifying the intended meaning would be time-consuming whereas normally we recognize each otherтАЩs communicative intentions quickly and easily.

3.2. Indirect peech acts as idioms?

Another line of explanation of indirect speech acts was brought forward by Jerrold Sadock [42, 197]. According to his theory, indirect speech acts are expressions based on an idiomatic meaning added to their literal meaning (just like the expression тАЬto pushup daisiesтАЭ has two meanings: тАЬto increase the distance of specimens of Bellis perennis from the center of the earth by employing forceтАЭ and тАЬto be deadтАЭ). Of course, we do not have specific idioms here, but rather general idiom schemes. For example, the scheme тАЬCan you + verb?тАЭ is idiomatic for commands and requests.

However, the idiomatic hypothesis is questionable as a general strategy. One problem is that a reaction to an indirect speech act can be composite to both the direct and the indirect speech act, e.g.

The speaker: Can you tell me the time?

The hearer: Yes, itтАЩs three oтАЩclock.

We never find this type of reaction to the literal and the idiomatic intepretation of an idiom:

The speaker: Is he pushing the daisies by now?

Hearer 1: Yes/no (the idiomatic meaning is taken into account).

Hearer 2: Depends what you mean. As a gardener, yes (the literal meaning is taken into account).

Another problem is that there is a multitude of different (and seemingly semantically related) forms that behave in a similar way:

a)Can you pass me the salt?

) Could you pass me the salt?

c)May I have the salt?

d) May I ask you to pass the salt?

e) Would you be so kind to pass the salt?

f) Would you mind passing the salt?

Some of these expressions are obviously semantically related (e.g. can/could, would you be so kind/would you mind), and it seems that it is this semantic relation that makes them express the same indirect speech act. This is different for classical idioms, where the phrasing itself matters:

a) topush the daisies тАЬto be deadтАЭ vs. to push the roses

b) tokick the bucket тАЬto dieтАЭ vs. to kick the barrel.

Hence, a defender of the idiom hypothesis must assume a multitude of idiom schemes, some of which are obviously closely semantically related.

Summarizing, we can say that there are certain cases of indirect speech acts that have to be seen as idiomatized syntactic constructions (for example, English why not-questions.) But typically, instances of indirect speech acts should not be analyzed as simple idioms.

3.3. Other approaches to the problem

The difference of the idiomatic and inference approaches can be explained by different understanding of the role of convention in communication. The former theory overestimates it while the latter underestimates it, and both reject the qualitative diversity of conventionality. Correcting this shortcoming, Jerry Morgan writes about two types of convention in indirect speech acts [39, 261]:conventions of language and conventions of usage. The utterance тАЬCan you pass the salt?тАЭ cannot be considered as a regular idiom (conventions of language), but its use for an indirect request is undoubtedly conventional, i.e. habitual for everyday speech that is always characterized by a certain degree of ritualization.

In accordance with this approach the function of an indirect speech act is conventionally fixed, and an inference process is not needed. Conventions of usage express what Morgan calls тАЬshort-circuited implicaturesтАЭ: implicatures that once were motivated by explicit reasoning but which now do not have to be calculated explicitly anymore.

There is an opinion that indirect speech acts must be considered as language polysemy, e.g. тАЬWhy not + verb?тАЭ construction serves as a formal marker of not just the illocutive function of a question, but of that of a request, e.g. тАЬWhy not clean the room right now?тАЭ

According to Grice and Searle, the implicit meaning of an utterance can always be inferred from its literal meaning. But according to the relevance theory developed by Sperber and Wilson [46, 113], the process of interpretation of indirect speech acts does not at all differ from the process of interpretation of direct speech acts. Furthermore, it is literal utterances that are often marked and sound less natural than utterances with an indirect meaning. For example, the utterance тАЬShe is a snake.тАЭhaving an implicit meaning sounds more natural than тАЬShe is spiteful.тАЭ Exclamatory utterances тАЬItтАЩs not exactly a picniс weather!тАЭ and тАЬItтАЩs not a day for cricket!тАЭ sound more expressive and habitual than the literal utterance тАЬWhat nasty weather we are having!тАЭ The interrogative construction expressing a request тАЬCould you put on your black dress?тАЭ is more customary than the performative: тАЬI suggest that you should put on your black dress.тАЭ

To summarize: there is no unanimity among linguists studying indirect speech acts as to how we discover them in each otherтАЩs speech and тАЬextractтАЭ their meaning. Every theory has got its strong and weak points, and the final word has not yet been said.

4. ILLOCUTIONS OF INDIVIDUAL UTTERANCES WITHIN

A DISCOURSE

Speech act theories considered above treat an indirect speech act as the product of a single utterance based on a single sentence with only one illocutionary point - thus becoming a pragmatic extension to sentence grammars. In real life, however, we do not use isolated utterances: an utterance functions as part of a larger intention or plan. In most interactions, the interlocutors each have an agenda; and to carry out the plan, the illocutions within a discourse are ordered with respect to one another. Very little work has been done on the contribution of the illocutions within utterances to the development of understanding of a discourse.

As Labov and Fanshel pointed out, тАЬmost utterances can be seen as performing several speech acts simultaneously .. Conversation is not a chain of utterances, but rather a matrix of utterances and actions bound together by a web of understandings and reactions .. In conversation, participants use language to interpret to each other the significance of the actual and potential events that surround them and to draw the consequences for their past and future actions.тАЭ (Labov, Fanshel 1977: 129).

Attempts to break out of the sentence-grammar mould were made by Labov and Fanshel [35], Edmondson [29], Blum-Kulka, House, and Kasper [24]. Even an ordinary and rather formal dialogue between a customer and a chemist contains indirectness (see table 4.1).

Table 4.1

Indirect speech acts of an ordinary formal dialogue

ParticipantUtteranceIndirect speech acts
Customer

Do you have any

Actifed?

Seeks to establish preparatory condition for

transaction and thereby implies the intention to

buy on condition that Actifed is available.

ChemistTablets or linctus?

Establishes a preparatory condition for the

transaction by offering a choice of product.

Customer

Packet of tablets,

please.

Requests one of products offered, initiates

transaction. In this context, even without

тАЬpleaseтАЭ, the noun phrase alone will function as

a requestive.

ChemistThat'll be $18.50.

A statement disguising a request for payment to

execute the transaction.

CustomerOK.

Agrees to contract of sale thereby fulfilling

t buyer's side of the bargain.

ChemistHave a nice day!

Fulfills seller's side of the bargain and

concludes interaction with a conventional farewell.

Вместе с этим смотрят:


A Farewell to Arms


A history of the english language


About England


Accommodation in St.Petersburg


Acquaintance with geometry as one of the main goals of teaching mathematics to preschool children